Appendix II
Prolegomena to Any Future
Noumenology
David C. Braun
© 2006 David C. Braun
Appendix II
What follows is not primary to but
dependent on the system; its separation from the main might rob it of a certain
force, if not of its intelligibility. I
thus deemed its inclusion the only practical solution to the problem of how to
articulate it. The text will also assume
what is but by hint shown before it as to ethical, religious and political
matters. I realize that the risks of
such inclusions are present, but deem it appropriate, especially given the
heated discussions of related issues at present, to venture my thoughts as set
forth in the sequel (to the extent they would be at all helpful, though I fear
they may be provocative of more recriminations than reflections).
I
The relation among persons
found in government, that of power, has been criticized in the more recent past
as being per se wrongful or
wrongheaded. Those who, as much in
opposition to conservative proponents of past injustice as in opposition to
anarchists opposed to such and other injustices, defend government point out
that the theory of ethics, not satisfied with its own elucidation in abstracto, suggests our transit to
practice with its own urgency. Our
practice of virtue and fairness leads to provision for the needs of the common
life (the result of harmonic love), needs such as those occasioned by the emergencies
of natural disaster and economic dislocations in which an ordered response is
more adequate to the task these needs set before us. Such an organization executing an ordered
response in an ethical fashion can be used to bring order in general to our
common life, which ought to be according to order; whence the advent of law and
of its enforcement of the ethical as the truly orderly way.
But this argument, catering
patently to the noble moral predisposition toward alleviating every sort of
malady (including tragedies without fault), seems at best artificial. Worse, it may call for more government than
needed, to the extent private organizations could conceivably discharge such
functions. Some activities now generally
governmental were under the aegis of private bodies or of public opinion. Only by convenience, arguably, would
government assume such functions. Although the lack of taxing authority would
be a telling argument for our needing a government to discharge some of the
contemplated functions, it seems to pale in light of the voluntary nature of
many forms of tax collection or of the lack of compliance therewith in general.[1] (Arguably taxation is nearly on a par with,
e.g., tithing, but for the threat of prosecution and incarceration for those
who fail to comply with the tax laws.)
Arguably, moreover, the aid of many good-natured people and the presence
of community opinion may supplant (in some ethical community) the lack of
taxing power.
Does the above projected (if
not also real) debate provide the answer to the question of the morality of the
power relation? Is the power relation
nearly as unavoidable as the need to exercise certain bodily functions,
rendering the above debate meaningless?
Specifically, if I am to eat, I next need to acquire; my acquiring
presupposes the concept of property if I am not to fight my neighbor (for
example, over food sufficient for one).
Property-allocation, however, assumes the exercise of power in relation
to things recognized as property. For me
to say, “This is mine; do not touch it,” is to coerce any other and thus to
exercise power. Unless I decide to cease
eating altogether, I should very much require a system of property, and
self-starvation’s morality is, I think, at best dubious. Accordingly, I can hardly cancel the power
relation morally; the question becomes one of how it should be exercised.[2] Anarchism thus becomes, at best, a form of
“unorganized self-government” (a contradiction); otherwise it is either an
unrealistic temptation or a vision of the celestial New Jerusalem.
If I cannot avoid the power
relation or coercion, my question is in relation to its legitimate
exercise. Hereof the only considerable response
from the ethical standpoint necessarily involves the consent of the coerced to
that power relation expressed as rule or government, as a starting point; that
will must be ethical. One can have
government without law (Pol Pot’s Kampuchea, for example, had government but
hardly law) or law without government (e.g., the Torah in the shtetl operated
by consent and without a power-wielding government as we know it). But as the power relation without the order
or the ethical is neither useful nor ultimately ethical, government must
involve the rule of law. Anarchism and
law are not entirely antithetical, though law tends toward the coercion that
anarchism tends to disdain.
We are also familiar with the
right of the individual human, as a free entity, to live as free, to think and
believe freely, to control his or her own destiny, to have such personal
liberty respected by others, this being that person’s endowment by right and
(in theology’s perspective) given by God.
We hold this liberty, which includes the liberty of conscience (free
exercise of religion) to be what our ethic requires us to observe because it is
under the head of love and respect (which are harmonic, in that my recognition
of the other as a free moral agent requires me to give it such).[3] Moreover, as God would aid religion to the
extent required to protect it from error, so as not to have us lost by error or
being in disharmony with the way intended, even by inadvertence or by excusable
ignorance, yet God does not waste such special gifts where reason can suffice,
e.g., in the natural sphere. We ascribe
no such protection, then, to any unaided magisterium
on its own, especially in transcendent matters we cannot meet by mere
empiresis, experiment, hypothesis, ratiocination or mathematics.[4] Hence
our ordering of the common life and our religious life we entrust, on our own
or by divine direction, to appropriately distinct organizations. By principle we keep the rule of the common
life, its constitution and its organization out of the religious bodies’
affairs and vice-versa, so that, no
matter our belief in religion, we may enjoy the benefits each provides to our
community in harmony.
Our body of ethical precepts
and corollaries therefrom (i.e., our constitution and laws, for what is law but
our tool for engendering order by competent, accepted authority, and what is
order but harmony?) we desire to retain in consistent form, as we premise it in
whole upon the harmonic. We should
therefore be disturbed if our development of this body of precepts and
corollaries were ever to show a contradiction, the sign not of mere error but
(for our ethic) of the unethical. Such a
contradiction we should seek to remove, preferably by examining the root of our
going into contradiction to see if it is mandated by and inevitably issued from
our harmonic ethic. We could find our
contradiction to be only a false one; however, we could find ourselves in a
position not unlike that of God confronted with human freedom and abuse of that
freedom. Such a problem we would find
not soluble but merely endurable.
Whatever problem we find and however we find we must either deal or live
with it, we will have to bring before the community, i.e., all of the people of
sufficient age and judgment, in virtue of their freedom, which must be
respected in this enterprise affecting them.
But beyond our above principles we find our way into difficulties, as
will appear in the sequel.
I caution the reader not every
law is necessarily an ethical or moral matter, as some laws treat of matters
ethically adiaphoric in nature.[5] Nor is every law without exception ethical or
just; South Africa’s former system of constitutional apartheid was riddled with injustice throughout. I treat herein
ends, not facts; accordingly I offer no detailed jurisprudence directed toward
the minutiae of the law (taken
specifically or jurisdictionally). I suspect no such theory can be offered that
does not stray into a fundamentally alien field of public policy, a field not
to be confused with the philosophy of law, the only interest to be served
herein, only (moreover) insofar as it is related to the general theory of
ethical value.
II
To the
extent law is the system of rules enacted or announced by competent authorities
(responsible under the constitution to the constituent population as a whole)
for securing order and justice, it is law in the fullest sense of the term when
it is according to harmony and is fully so only insofar as it conforms to the
ethical obligations called natural law or the law of reason.[6] This law, moreover, must respect the rights
of other free
wills, i.e., the rights to exercise free will in relation to that individual,
if it is to be harmonic. As every person is an ethical or moral agent (I pass
not on sanctity), law cannot be fully law except according to a constitution
from the people for the government of their affairs. Such a constitution must likewise respect the
free will of the governed, including the rights of freedom of speech, assembly,
petition, the press, and of religion and the conscience (which, for religion,
must be unconstrained so as better to honor God from the heart). To secure these rights, government cannot
decide how people are to think or believe, and in matters not of the immanent
government ought to maintain a studied neutrality because of its lack of
competence and, even more importantly, because any forays by the collective
into the area of belief must necessarily abridge freedom of others in some way,
and would give rise to an occasion of offense against the rights of
others. Even the atheist has the right
to agree to the constitution on principle, not necessarily by compromise, as
does any believer; this can be only by a neutral pact. Every free person’s rights to freedom and its
exercise in general is to be protected, including the rights in relation to his
or her life, as essential part of its exercise in the republic.
The problem arises in relation
to the several rights and conditions for the most orderly and rational system.
It pits liberty so against the rational basis for law that it is
insoluble. Therefore I call it the
Antinomy of
Jurisprudential Reason. We understand
that there are conflicts between various concepts of liberty and law under a
constitution (e.g., freedom from unreasonable warrantless searches and seizures
and the right to continuing privacy as protection from public exposure as
continuing invasion of privacy against the interest of government in
apprehending and punishing offenders to protect society as a whole). Such disputes are usually balanced on the
basis of facts and on the weight assigned to each interest according to a rule
(e.g., absolute protection from invasion, protection except against regulations
strictly necessary to effectuate compelling state interests, protection except
against regulations reasonably related to substantial interests, or protection
except against regulations reasonably related to legitimate state
interests). But the Antinomy set forth
below seems not to allow a solution totally satisfactory.
Antinomy of
Jurisprudential Reason
Thesis
Every constitution guaranteeing
freedom and due process of law as harmonic order assumes the dual premises of
the reality of the world and the true freedom of the will (cf. the notion of voluntary activity in relation to criminal
responsibility, or in relation to ability to conform and not to endanger
oneself or others so as to avoid civil commitment), which assume or contain the
further premise of the reality of God (as ultimate Guarantor thereof).[7] Without these assumptions and their content,
we cannot meaningfully propound and live by such a system, which becomes
absurd. As God is the necessary Basis
hereof, all rights are rights except as against the plenary divine right over
transcendent affairs, including the right to apportion human life against even
the ego’s right over itself in privacy. Hence suicide and assisting a clearly
voluntary suicide must be contrary to order and law and not rights.
Antithesis
Every constitution guaranteeing
freedom and due process of law as harmonic order requires the full protection
of the free, unfettered and uncoerced will in matters of belief, and must thus
be grounded on independent principles of a religiously neutral nature in order
to command rational assent and to be developed as a rational system of rationes decidendi (et oboediendi) for
the necessarily pluralistic free society. Thus God’s reality cannot be taken as
a premise for such a constitution or the law thereunder. As God cannot be taken
as the Basis hereof, all rights must be held judicially to be rights even
against a plenary divine “right” over transcendent affairs, including the right
to apportion human life, so as to protect the ego’s privacy over itself Hence
suicide and assisting a clearly voluntary suicide must be consistent with
constitutional order, as rights.
III
The Thesis gives mere personal
(as opposed to public) grounds for assent to the system; the Antithesis seeks
simply the necessary conditions for having a harmonic intersubjective system
taken on its internal terms for each participant, one of which is the necessary
inviolability of each individual, taken as real. But the consensus’ belief,
though based in theory on the universal union of “organic human body” with
“principle of free will” which makes one human,[8]
can be and is overthrown oft by the explicit grounding of (new) constitutions,
interpretations and decrees of governments.[9] Where human liberty is contingent on such a
suspension’s absence where its possibility is not excluded, no liberty is
safe. One’s taking the Thesis as a
merely private ratio oboediendi leaves
only an arbitrary, capricious ground for respect for humanity and for
preservation of human life and liberty with respect to the question of who or
what is a person for the purposes of the law.
Thus the argument of the Thesis is necessary to the guarantee of
liberty. And, as against the self, the
law cannot allow the frustration of free will as to its public operation, the
consequence of, e.g., avoidable demise without treatment or of suicide. But that construction serves to overthrow the
paramount nature of the will as ground for the law with respect to the
government’s right to frame a law.
But if I invoke it as other
than a private jurisprudence, as a ratio
decidendi, I do so at the risk of negating at the root the possibility of a
pluralist constitution. I must thus unequivocally outlaw the kaishaku[10] even
though he acts according to his faith; I must also require judges to affirm in
rulings of the courts what they may not personally be able to hold. (How differs this from the law’s compelling a
Muslim who is a judge in America to award statutory interest on a judgment, or
a Catholic who is a judge to grant a divorce where the evidence is sufficient
for it?) State promulgation of a belief
such as this would be state-ecclesiasticism; I can divine therefrom, through
the educational functions of government (functions reasonably related to
avoiding pauperism among the great mass of the population and to equalizing
their opportunities in society — to say nothing of the function of law itself,
in part to educate the public as to behavior permitted or forbidden), the
implications against liberty of conscience and of familial education of
children. For if the ground of respect
of personal dignity is the state-professed idea of God, invariably that idea
must enter into education. Above all,
the nonreligious cannot participate in such a ratio status unless it really becomes naught more than a mere positivism already
characterized by the Antithesis, a positivism[11]
potentially in opposition to the ratio of
the Thesis. (If the constitution of an
officially theistic land has no religious test for the judiciary, its theism is
but lip-service and its true jurisprudence is of the Antithesis, at least with
respect to such a judge.)
IV
All law rests on the premise of
the coercion of liberty. Not only is
criminal law coercion of liberty (if you kill, rape, steal, etc., we will
imprison, fine or execute you), but so is civil law (if you fail to pay
damages, execution will be had against your property; or if you fail to pay
support or to obey a court order or subpoena as directed, you will be adjudged
in contempt and may be incarcerated), to the extent that behind an order in a
case may lie a veiled threat. The law
exists to enforce uniformity and conformity of behavior in many spheres as well
as to protect and adjust rights and to effect the orderly provision for the
general welfare. It restrains the
malefactors, contract breachers, trespassers and unfair dealers; it does not
merely pass out the benefits of organized society.
As the Antinomy questions the
problem of coercion of the will by restraining the willing and their aiders and
abettors from carrying out suicide, note that here the contradiction
arises. Coercion we use here to protect
natural rights (the only possible premise of the right to commit suicide),
which must arise from the purely moral-theological ground, along with the very
legitimacy of the use of coercion. The
Antinomy implicitly assumes that coercion is always legitimate to accomplish
the just, harmonic purposes of the law.
But this assumption remains unexamined in the case here presented,
implicitly always accepted, without statement of the conditions for the
legitimate application of the rule allowing coercion. This could serve to eliminate the Antinomy with respect to the
immediate question of suicide rights, without having to decide whether we must
write into the law a justification grounded explicitly on the premise of a
Divinity (the principle of neutrality in matters of religious belief to the
contrary notwithstanding). In other
cases of the rights of persons, we would be able to decide affirmatively in favor
of their paramount rights under a rule of benefit of the doubt,[12] because the very
orderliness of law would otherwise be jeopardized, when any life or liberty
could be snuffed out at whim.
The Antinomy indicates that the
law by its nature cannot answer the fundamental questions. At best, all one can
officially say, without courting it, is that the law in a just, free society
must assume the dignity of an apparently rational, sapient species (hence all
its members, counted according to the benefit-of-all-doubts rule) and that only
by assuming that and the reality of the other persons as given will a social
compact in a free society be possible. We are nevertheless left without a ratio decidendi for prohibiting a
clearly voluntary suicide (or the assistance of such suicide), assuming that
using the coercive power of the state would be appropriate in such an area.
This appears to render argument that such laws do not offend the due process
clause difficult if not impossible, though suicide generally is disfavored
culturally and raises substantial questions regarding fraud against insurers
and pauperization of a suicide’s dependents.
* * *
N.B. The position taken in the Antithesis was
written before the Supreme Court of the United States handed down its ruling in
Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S.
702 (1997), holding that there is no constitutionally protected right to
physician-assisted suicide. Chief
Justice Rehnquist, in the majority opinion, balked altogether at recognizing
constitutionally a right that had flown in the face of over two centuries of
American common-law tradition (based on five prior centuries of the English
common law) and subsequent legislative prohibitions by practically every state.
The opinion is notable for an altogether inexcusable dearth of discussion of
the constitutionally recognized right to bodily self-determination. That right the Court first recognized in Union Pacific Railway Company v. Botsford, 141
U.S. 250, 251 (1891). The Court would later elaborate the contours of that right
at further length in Griswold v.
Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1964), Roe
v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973), and their progeny. Justice Souter, while
discussing the privacy-related right to bodily self-determination, was
concerned with the potential for erosion of the so-called right to
physician-assisted suicide into voluntary or involuntary euthanasia. To
avoid the dim prospect of a doctor’s thus getting into euthanasia, Justice
Souter raised the specter of euthanasia as a basis for finding a compelling
state interest that would outweigh an asserted fundamental right. Justice Stevens, while inviting continuing
debate on the issue, deemed the issues of mental depression and family pressure
to weigh as factors justifying the Court’s finding compelling interests to
outweigh such a right. It is confessedly
not the office of a philosopher to prescribe to that august Court how it ought
to rule on any given issue. But the
philosopher cannot be blamed for wondering to what extent the Court did not
fail to make a coherent, well-reasoned body of thought on the question of
bodily self-determination in deciding that question of constitutional law. Nor can a thinker avoid comment on the
Court’s apparent embrace of the notion of the “sanctity of human life,” a shibboleth that comes close to raising
precisely the concerns addressed in the Antinomy. [I freely confess, without need for
“rendering,” that this note was written before the Supreme Court had brought
upon it a certain scandalous shame by issuing an opinion denying its own value
as precedent, in effect a “lawless” decision for a common-law jurisdiction
where stare decisis is a prime
rule. Bush v. Gore, 531 U.S. 98, 109 (2000). That shame resulted in the “election” (or,
better, “selection”), for the Republic, of a chief executive whose
administration, apparently as a matter of policy, countenanced the torturing
not only of truth but also even of human beings.]
[1]
One thinks of the voluntary nature of compliance with the laws regarding
federal income taxes and the filing of tax returns in the United States, or of
the commonness of tax avoidance in, e.g., Italy. However, even in Italy (as
well as in America) there are celebrated criminal cases brought against people
for tax evasion.
[2] I
do not mean to suggest that society does not have a “natural foundation” on the
basis of the human family, or that religious commandments to honor parents (as
accepted implicitly in one’s accepting the deposit of religious revelation
defined by the Catholic Church accepted on the basis of the signs discussed in
Appendix I) have no bearing on discussion regarding the obligation to obey
civil authority in matters wherein the moral law is not violated as a result.
But neither the Church nor I attempt to divine from such commandments a theory
of the state. Moreover, were one to
attempt to devise a theory of the state therefrom, one may indulge an occasion
of immoral conduct or belief, such as racism or the bloody nationalism that
cost all too many lives without bestowing any particular benefits in several
wars of the twentieth century.
[3]
The reader should turn to §30 of the main text for the discussion of harmony
and love as to be valued, as also to §25 regarding personal freedom and §21
regarding the reality of God.
[4]As to the magisterium of the Church, see Appendix I. The “unaided magisterium” I used to refer to the state specifically as unaided
judge in matters of faith and morals, whether by the arm of an official state
Church that cannot lay claim to other than human foundation (as, e.g., the
Church of England) or otherwise. I mean
also by the same token to express clearly that the Catholic Church cannot
rightfully claim, by virtue of its plenary authority to define the deposit of
revelation in matters of faith and morals, to invade the field, e.g., of
science, an invasion not necessary as God has given humanity adequate natural
instruments for such a task, a point already hinted at in §22.
[5] I
draw attention, e.g., to the niceties of the rules of procedure as such, or to
the legal prerequisites for making a gift, or to such points as the doctrine of
worthier title.
[6] As the last paragraph of
the prior section had suggested, I read no minutiae
from the concept of natural law I frame, and therefore hold it does not
reach several questions at all. I recognize that “natural law” has been used at
times to attack legislation wholly salutary and ethical in my reckoning, e.g.,
the child labor laws (on the premise that employers had a natural right to
employ whom they pleased). “Natural law”
has also been employed to advance an agenda abhorrent to those who would have
joined in attacks on the child labor laws; this turnabout has engendered the
charge that natural law is but a prostitute, a charge leveled against the law
itself as well.
[7] As
§29 of the main work made clear, resort to the veracity of God must be made ere
I may conclude that the world of sense is to be trusted or that the other it
presents is as given, whose intelligible activity represents a separate and
free intelligence appearing through its activity (e.g., language) to betoken at
once the state of being bound to sense-experience and that of a freedom
analogous to mine. Moreover, freedom of
activity is not proper to an entity which cannot choose not to be, if all
things are a se and are inherently
active (see §21). Hence freedom likewise is created by God.
[8]
This was acknowledged by legal authorities as early as Sir William Blackstone
in his Commentaries on the Common Law of
England (9th ed., 1783), vol. I, p. 125 (“The absolute rights of
man, considered as a free agent.., are usually summed up in one general
appellation, and denominated the natural liberty of mankind.., being a right
inherent in us by birth, and one of the gifts of God to man at his creation,
when he endued (sic) him with the
faculty of free-will”); id. at 129
(“The rights [of Englishmen] ... consist in a number of private immunities;
which will appear, from what has been premised, to be indeed no other, than
either the residuum of natural liberty... or else those civil privileges, which
society hath engaged to provide, in lieu of the natural liberties so given up
by individuals”).
[9]E.g., Dred Scott v. Sanford, 60 U.S. (9 How.) 393 (1857); the Endlösung of the
Hitler régime; cf. perhaps also Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973). The last-mentioned involves the difficulty of
determining when, in contemplation of the law, the fetus is to be recognized as
human, given that the state has a compelling interest in protecting the lives
of human beings, as the Roe Court
acknowledged. The difficulty the Court
did not recognize was that it thereby appeared to arrogate to itself a position
not materially different from that of the Dred
Scott Court, i.e., the Court played God.
[10]The
kaishaku assists in performing seppuku, i.e., ritual suicide, by using
the long sword to behead the suicide should the latter hesitate to complete the
act. Among Japanese whose lives are
regulated by bushido, the code of the
warrior, and whose religious orientation is rooted either in Buddhism or in
Shinto, to act in such a capacity was an honor.
Western European attitudes towards suicide are rooted essentially in the
ethic of Catholicism, which regarded suicide as a mortal sin evidencing despair
of salvation and total rejection of life — and salvation — from God, and denied
the suicide burial in consecrated ground unless the suicide (if that were what
had occurred) could be laid to insanity.
A related attitude occurs in Judaism, which regards suicide (where
committed in circumstances where it is not elected as an option in lieu of
apostasy, hence a form of martyrdom) to be hillul
ha-Shem, blasphemy against the Name.
[11]Herein legal positivism, i.e.,
the view that law (including personal rights) is but the positive enactment,
whether by constitution, statute, rule of procedure or case law of the courts
(in jurisdictions where the common-law tradition is followed to any extent), is
meant.
[12]Several have pointed out
that the attempt to protect the fetus as a person essentially requires enacting
a religious tenet (when ensoulment occurs) into law, an act inconsistent with
the necessarily pluralistic basis for constituting a free society. Cf,
e.g., Webster v. Reproductive Health Services,
492 U.S. 490, 566 (1989)(Stevens, J., concurring and dissenting). A benefit-of-doubts enactment would appear,
moreover, to allocate a burden of proof away from the government toward the
individual in criminal cases, similarly problematic for a free society even if
that theory (or a religious one) were but underpinning for a constitutional
amendment. (Where society requires the
accused to prove his or her innocence, it is not far from compelling a person
to incriminate himself or herself and not far from “the rack and the
thumbscrew.”) The difficulty regarding
the benefit-of-all-doubts rule is nevertheless equally present in quite nearly
any case involving killing of what the government alleges is a human being as,
firstly, that the other is actually as given is provable only upon drawing from
philosophical theology. The law cannot
but assume that those appearing as other persons are in fact other human
persons possessing free choice, persons entitled to treatment as res sacrae, as possessing the dignity of
a human being whose life may not in the ordinary course of events be taken
except under extreme circumstances. The circumstances that ought to obtain
before taking of life may be at allowed generally involve, in point of law, the
strict necessity of taking that person’s life in self-defense (I prescind for
the moment from the justification that taking life was necessary to prevent the
commission of a forcible felony, statutorily authorized in several
jurisdictions, and from discussion of the “castle” doctrine regarding one’s
right to use deadly force in defense of self or others or to prevent a forcible
felony when one has a right to be in his or her home superior to that of the
victim), with good reason, as self-preservation is one of the basic laws of
organic life, and as minimal intrusion into another’s rights for such purpose
is consistent with a general harmonic ethic cognizant of divine proprietary
rights and the rights of others. But,
given that allowance, one is constrained to ask whether a contemplated killing
under any circumstance is morally licit, a question arching over into
determination of questions such as the justice of collective killing of one
person (judicial execution) or of a group (war). A minimally-intrusive allowance for
self-defense appears to be the only rule consistent with the foregoing, and
tends to mandate at a minimum the more sophisticated theory of bellum iustum current in Catholic
theology before conscientious objection gained acceptance and to require even
more restrictions regarding capital punishment than current under Proffitt v. Florida, 428 U.S. 242
(1976). As a resolution of the abortion question, one wonders whether, in light
of developments regarding in vitro fertilization
and like achievements, a tertium quid might
be available to allow termination of pregnancy without death of the fetus.
0 Comments:
Post a Comment
Subscribe to Post Comments [Atom]
<< Home