Chapter IV
Prolegomena to Any Future Noumenology
David C. Braun
David C. Braun
© 2006 David C. Braun
Chapter IV
16
[A. From “within the charmed circle” of
consciousness and its system; issues and alternatives:]
[i. Many-valued logic;
contradiction, harmony, and definiteness:]
To the extent one works from within time (as opposed
to sempiternity), indeterminate future events have no definite nature. Statements concerning them are properly
neither true nor false. Neither
prophecies nor matters allegedly known by precognition come under this rule;
assent to either can be based on showing the determined character, as
revelation or as a reliable faculty, of an issuer of the statement in question. Where the real referent of any statement is
indefinite (whether because of an undetermined future system or because of my
confronting an indeterminate entity, e.g., a microcosmic physical entity in
quantum mechanics), not only will such a three-valued logic apply but the rule of
contradiction fails to apply to such indeterminates. This cannot be said of any proposition
whereof the truth-value is definite; for such both the law of noncontradiction
and the law of the excluded middle apply because of the harmony of the
definitude. For this reason the independent harmony allows use of these laws in
relation to the transcendent to which that independent harmony points.
[ii.
Phenomenalism’s inadequacy:]
In
holding phenomenalism inadequate, ad
interim I accept at very least that science is supposed to seek “truth”
(witness the problem of motion of the earth or the sun). I do not sense the
revolution of the earth or its axial rotation in Copernican or Keplerian
fashion. Only by invoking the transphenomenal
can I learn that either occurs even should it by explaining other phenomena
show its correspondence to the most inclusively coherent phenomenally-based
object-system. Science must assume such
objects, yet neither it nor any philosophy (absente
noumenologia) can justly arrive at the assumed object. Second, a specific case within phenomena
leads one to regard the phenomenalist view with suspicion; when one drinks
alcohol to excess one accepts alcohol as cause of the affected state of
consciousness, though any such causal relationship must treat the ground of
consciousness as an object in the world of other independently existing objects
in no wise contingent on the conscious, which this view can never
substantiate. Yet such a view is of the
greatest use to (e.g.) the healer or toxicologist. Arguably I imply there is a noumenon in my
asking about a world existing outside me or about truth. Is “truth” a
meaningless bit of babble? I insist on
watching the answer; it has consequences for the possibility of a credible
neuropsychology or neurotoxicology. Is
knowledge really the lore of truth or on the level of the crystal ball and the
astrologer’s predictions? (Toxicology
asserts, for example, that the conscious has a ground subject to laws, yet the
denial of noumenology suggests somewhat the contrary, for if the connection
between the harmonic and God be truthful there can be no such thing as
transcendent harmony without the possibility of noumenology, and at any rate
such harmony would be unknowable.)
To the
above I add that consciousness is twofold as both waking consciousness and not
necessarily harmonic dream-consciousness. I submit for consideration (e.g.) the
question of Zhuangze whether one having dreamt of becoming a butterfly were
really a butterfly dreaming it was a human.
Were I so to dream, could I have a harmonic self-knowledge or knowledge
of other objects, or would harmonic knowledge be an error? Why should I give any priority in knowledge
to the harmonic or noncontradictory, thus segregating the inconsistent material
of dreams to a separate compartment for later analysis in terms of an
objective, harmonic theory founded either upon notions of the harmonic
deep-structure or of a ground of consciousness influenced by yet other
independent objects? The undergirding of
phenomenalism can give no answer whatever thereto; this failure in an area
important not merely to the possibility of self-knowledge but to that of any
knowledge manifests the bankruptcy of phenomenalism, though absente noumenologia it would be the
only tenable theory. The obvious further
question is whether one can predict a future event in scientific fashion (e.g.,
the trajectory of a moving object) on the basis of prior phenomena, given the
dependence of such prediction on harmonic laws.
[iii.
The self as “limit” of the world or as ground of the world:]
The
notions of the subject’s circumscribing the world and the nonexhaustibility of
objects lend themselves to challenge of the harmony. Thereto I reply that the solipsistic
reduction of all to consciousness requires placing the experience’s root aliquomodo in my consciousness, against
which this thing found independent of my consciousness is elucidated, even as
independent of any part of my consciousness, according to the rules of harmonic
connection therein, so that something in the “world” is not mine by
origin. (If one takes “world” in the
sense of mere phenomena, perhaps the “beyond-my-world” would put it better.)
One
might discuss the ground of consciousness (from which the harmony independent
of consciousness is found to be independent), notwithstanding the idea that the
metaphysical self is the limit of the world, because of the harmonic rule of
causation, as long as it is taken to be identical with the cogito. One might,
incidentally, place psychology beyond the pale (i.e., of phenomenalism) to the
extent it applied causation to the “preconscious ego” it supposes, so that one
could never establish the independence from consciousness of any experience of
harmony, all such of which would be merely events of consciousness. But if the question is whether they are bare
phenomena of harmony perhaps not otherwise so, the causation by the cogito of the stripped harmony comes to
be a relevant and dispositive issue.
Thus I eliminate projects of the cogito
as grounds of the harmonic event in question to arrive at the independence
thereof
A
transcendental ego, never experienced but necessary concomitant of all
experience and thought and giving rise alike to the experienced self and the
world of experience, is reminiscent of the foregoing on the self as a
transcendental subject, the limit of one’s world, even though sketched in what
was otherwise a rejection of metaphysics. Interestingly, one of the proponents
of the transcendental ego rejected the noumenon allegedly because to do so
would save human freedom. Rejection of
philosophy without the independence of harmony raises the prospect that if
there is no noumenon the world of my experience is as real as I am. If objects of experience are only in and for
consciousness, they have yet the same basis for reality as have I. Indeed, the self of the I-think is a causal
construct, as are objects, to the extent not held during conscious observation,
as are “occult causes.” (If I grant an
occult cause like, e.g., an atom, have I not an object subject to laws? Then why live by the constraint against
applying causation beyond experience as reason for rejecting argument for the
reality of God?) The other position,
admitting that phenomena were objects in and for the subject and ground of the
organic body that, in turn, constituted the brain and mind of the individual
self, accepts as noumenon the transcendent[al] self as anterior to and outside
the principle of causation, of determinism, of sufficient reason, thus free,
unrestrained, blind, undifferentiated will.
Either position assumes (to a certain extent) a causal agency, occult in
nature, the ground of experience or its sine
qua non that is in esse continuous
aside from experience, an assumption unwarranted without the independent
harmony (for which I have no possibility of scientific experiment to
establish).
[iv.
The “other:”]
Without
independent harmony I can conclude nothing transcendently, such as a ground
beyond any sensation thereof. While the
existence of the consciousness not my own as ground of the behaviors I
encounter in the “form of the other” cannot be inferred without assuming the
transcendent application of the laws of noncontradiction and of causation, the
same can be said of a “ground of my consciousness.” While the cogito
identifies a definitional constant of experience, its constant
identification with a definitional nonvoid I call the ego, the persistence of
the self as a ground of consciousness, to the proof of which the cogito aspires, is facilitated only by
my being allowed both cited principles beyond sensation, a conclusion allowable
only within the noumenology, if at all.
Without the independent harmony at all, one could say that the other
existed with as much right as one could say (s)he existed. That self and other both exist in one
consciousness, however, one would have to say in the premises, in the only
sense one could then meaningfully give to “exist,” even though one could still
speak of the “self’ (now the subject of consciousness) in a nonpsychological
way as a metaphysical subject, the limit of the world. (An attempt to argue that otherness is a
necessary condition of my objectivity assumes that I have objectivity, an
assumption unwarranted absent noumenology.)
How one
answers the challenge, “Prove to me you exist,” depends on the meanings of
“prove,” “you” and “exist.” Is proof by
a preponderance of evidence, by clear and convincing evidence, beyond a
reasonable doubt or beyond all doubt, even a speculative doubt? By “you” do I mean merely a configuration as
in and for experience or another person (i.e., in the way that I am a
person)? Is “exist” to be taken as
“present for my experience” (in which event proof of a configuration in my
experience is unnecessary), or does it refer to some entity which is as such
even outside my experiencing it? I could
as well challenge myself to prove my own existence especially if I mean the
latter. The Cartesian cogito may be no help here, if by “I”
should be meant not the activity I call “consciousness;” were that the self, or implied ego of the cogito, that famous argument would be superfluous because the ego would be a definition, though then I
would have a being that dissolved at night and then ex nihilo was restored to being on waking or dreaming. If I mean to show the existence of some
ground of the cogito (which must be
what Descartes meant), I must have recourse to that which allows me to apply
the category of cause beyond all experience.
(I do not experience the ground of the cogito or transcendental subject.)
Arriving thereat has been part of the point of the noumenological
travail. But not even that travail will
enable the limited other to prove to me, imprisoned in my world of sensation of
the same, its ground as ground of a like person, subsisting independently of my
sensing the same, which is commonly taken as the meaning of the challenge,
“Prove to me you exist,” if taken radically (as opposed to calling for proof
that one is as represented and not a persona fabricated for, e.g., illicit
purposes or those of espionage).
17
[B. Attempts to avoid noumenology:]
[i.
The linguistic short-cut against solipsism:]
Against
the whole of the foregoing endeavor one might object that no language of inner
sensations or private states may legitimately be used because one has no
assurance that the “harmony” of the past, for example, will not be what one now
calls “pain.” This would render constant
or regular speech thereabout impossible insofar as such speech cannot be
corrected by other persons. This might
be argued to overcome solipsism without resort to the elaborate trappings of
the noumenology, just as others would argue that personal objectivity’s
necessary condition is the reality of the other (without at all showing that
personal objectivity is altogether a truth-reflective notion). But if all cognitively meaningful speech
refers to experience, allowing that it may be explained through use, all
language might thus become unsure, as all experiences are internal; the
“publicization” of language is actually a secret version of transcendent
causality a priori and thus metaphysical.
Moreover, the solipsist cannot accept the basis of the argument, as
memory’s objects, experiences, are not (for the solipsist) in themselves but
alone for consciousness while it experiences them and are for it determined, so
that recapitulation of memories can be used and taken in definitions. This does not, however, run contrary to
noumenology’s effort to break out of the “prison of the subjective
givens.” One’s ability to perform that
altogether essential task is the most effective showing of phenomenalism’s
inadequacy as doctrine, though thereto could one add that the latter doctrine
can ill serve as foundation for secure knowledge in general, let alone that of
the self (cf. the dream of Zhuang
Zhou that he was a butterfly, and the difficulty of rational knowledge as
contingent on a harmony partially absent in, e.g., dream consciousness).
[ii. Physiology-based
efforts to find the transcendent:]
One can find all sorts of things
that, given causation, could be taken as independent of the ground of
consciousness, such as sudden, awakening events of nature or of others (a
thunderclap) or as events that infiltrate dreams. But the fact of independence from the mental
part of consciousness means not independence from consciousness in general, let
alone that the thing would be independent as harmony (or that one may take a
causal event outside consciousness as origin).
Similarly, from the vantage of the body (e.g., the back) one could by
moving change sensations in different surfaces thereof presented to an object
immediately. It would seem odd to
propose that these shifts of “arisings” in consciousness were arisings without
reference to an object outside but confronting some ground of my consciousness
(i.e., the body). But, considered from
the possibility of such experience’s being like a dream, without substance
outside consciousness, as by the question of Zhuangze, the question posed seems
to dissolve into the transcendent problem.
Moreover, it seems the occurrence I attribute to shifting my body
against the (unseen) surface confronted might be misinterpreted and involve a
host of fortuities that I suppose are of a continuity of object when I shift my
body in relation to “it.” This does not,
incidentally, vary materially the results won in the course of finding the
independent harmony. In connection
therewith, I ask whether sleep can be regarded as an overtaking of the
conscious by some deep-structural strike or as merely the tiring out of the
activity of consciousness. If the former
is the solution, it must assume causation but fails to yield an independent
harmony.
18
[B. (cont’d.):]
[iii. The harmony’s origin, and why the problem
must arise:]
Given
the rule that from harmony alone can come harmony, how can one hold otherwise
than that the harmony was of the transcendent real? How can the problem thereon arise upon the
realization of the unitive-extensive nature of the harmony? To be explicit, on what is my subjective
experience grounded if not on the harmonic?
Herein I note two problems. First
presented is that of the subjective notion of experience in general and of the
harmony therein; barring what is herein accomplished, one can arguably never
know a harmony not of the system which is the means of organizing sense data
within the transcendental ego, and within which (1) there must always be a
ground in harmony and (2) my perceived positive harmonies may (except for those
known to be independent and stripped) really be the harmony of repose in the
transcendental ego, plus the phenomenon in question. Second presented is that of the suggestion that
I have no knowledge of what the “transcendently real” world is like to the
extent that it is outside perception, and though I note a connection between
harmony and time, it could be that, outside the abstraction unto itself without
ground in harmony that is our harmonic world of the transcendental ego, things
are not in time but a blur of contradiction which cannot necessarily give rise
to the idea of causation. This state of
affairs obtains only to the extent that the harmonic is but the abstraction, the
system that is of the subjective and the transcendent ego manifesting itself
through consciousness. Upon my showing a
stripped harmony, independent thereof, I can finally come to the question of
that on which the harmony is grounded.
The
subjective system is harmonic in and for my consciousness, I can at least
prenoumenologically maintain, but that harmony might not apply beyond the level
of my consciousness, wherein things are “hard and fast” in their harmony. The condition for applying the rule of causation
is that there be something hard and fast in the harmony, and the rule is that
that which is on a certain level have, within the same level, a continuity, to
the extent that the same is harmonic.
“On the same level” refers to the problem of metasubjective extension of
purely subjective harmony. I read that harmony as hard and fast, though every
object having it could be no more than illusory. The harmony otherwise found may be really but
a repose state without positivity on its own, so that it is, of itself, no
commitment to a real metasubjective entity but a mere abstract system of
harmony, the system into which fit the phenomena revealed by the senses. One might think there is still the positing
activity of the thinking, sensing ego, which necessarily accompanies every
sensation or is affected by sensations come to it. This may be the positive entity which anchors
the system of harmony as it adheres to it.
But are not phenomena of consciousness variable, with the harmony being
also of the system, so that it is, once again, either of some transcendent,
harmonic thing real, or of the system that I called the subjective system of
the harmony?
It would
seem I have, on the one hand, a system of harmony and, on the other, a manifold
of otherwise possibly unordered phenomena, representing perhaps something other
than the things themselves. But the
system is on its own level, as it were; the idea that the disharmonic or
contradictory would lead to complete annihilation is itself of the harmonic
world of the hard and fast, so that I need not apply the idea of the community
of harmony and its interruption to negate the idea that the harmony is not to
be applied transcendently. Between the
harmonic system and the transcendent world would stand nothing; nothing would
connect them. Were I to hold that the
harmonic were positive harmony and were such as to be connected with the
transcendent and nonharmonic, I would then hold the untenable. But within its own level alone, one could
contend, it is the harmonic, hard and fast in harmony, that level being the
level of the purely subjective. I repeat
that I cannot derive the subjective system from a transcendent ground where the
reality I merely perceive as harmonic might be itself nonharmonic, even the
system.
The question
of the validity and origin of the harmony are intertwined thus. Harmony is of and within a subjective system,
which is but the totality of the harmony in and for itself and the perceiver
thereof I could not (per the ensuing theory) be able to say whereof it comes in
transcendent terms because I cannot say that the system has any transcendent
existence. Once that is conceded, the
law of the community of harmony applies.
The thing that is for me harmonic could be really otherwise, even that
which I know as the harmonic system. Even the so-called “transcendental ego”
can really be taken to be harmonic only within and for the system. Outside the system the hard-and-fast which I
had as present may not be so, in view of the time problem (time being perhaps
condensible unto a possible disharmony).
The very harmony and its system are, for the theory, harmonic only
within the system. But I find a harmony
independent as harmony as well as in its thinghood, stripped, wholly on its
side relating to me, thus harmonic not only for observer but also necessarily
for itself, so that I can assign it transcendent value. It is of the harmonic only and can have its
relation only with the harmonic as such, so that I am transcendently harmonic
and real. Without any independent
harmony I cannot assign a transcendently valued origin to the system of
harmony; I would know nothing but consciousness to which the law of harmony is
fitted or fits itself. A system that is
only for and within itself harmonic is a thing apart on its own level, perhaps
but an abstraction within an illusion. I
am tempted to apply the harmonic law, especially that of the community
extending to the prior or the ground, to give the system a ground in the transcendent,
so that it is also harmonic. So far I
had no entitlement to hold the harmonic as so in the thing, not merely for the
perceiver in the system, as long as harmony is manifested only in the
consciousness which is so for its self-contained system. Only after finding independent harmony can I
so apply it.
19
[B. (cont’d.):]
[iv.
Pragmatism’s inadequacy, or “Does it merely work, or is it the truth?”]
Why do I
go through this travail instead of blithely accepting the world in the face of
its being possibly “unreal?” Why should
I prefer the “true” (transcendent) over the “false?” What falsifies the “false?” Illusion (e.g., hallucination, mirage) is
surely not a subject of knowledge as that which is real is a subject of
knowledge. One might be able to show
how, at bottom, the preference for truth seems to be a value judgment, the
better to proceed to the preference for “that which succeeds in the realm of
thought.” [Science has widely been
hailed as successful; metaphysics seems to be a failure, thus deservedly (in
the view of disparagers) in disrepute.]
Aside from suspicions a pragmatic theory of thought of this kind invites
(e.g., the Ptolemaic theory seemed to “work” for its purposes), I think the
definitions of “true” and “real” too close to each other, in strict
lexicography, to jettison any sort of correspondence theory in favor of a
pragmatic theory not necessarily hitting at the object of knowledge. The “true state of affairs” I call “reality;”
thence is it legitimate to ask whether speech thereof is legitimate and whether
one can learn about reality. I note that
“true” and “real” both refer ultimately to the not-nothing, the not-illusory,
wherein I can trust.
20
[C. Special problems regarding the implications
of independent harmony:]
To the
above I add as the companion implication that the unanticipated configurations
of definitions are, as such, independent in their constitution of the
subjective system. As the configurations
of definitions result from the definitions and the harmony pervading them, the
rational configurations are truthful in themselves because of their coming from
independent harmony, of which the independent configurations are signs. The independence of harmony I seek likewise
to demonstrate that I may avoid any charge of being an imposer of harmony which
of itself is dependent on the subjective system. Objects as constituted in my experience (to
the extent perception is not of deception) in harmony of constancy in time,
even so constituted by consciousness historically, are also constituted in the
configurations independently in the world.
The same is dependent also on lack of disharmony evident in the means of
perception, especially such as is anticipated or explicable in terms of the
system (e.g., a dream, or a drug-induced hallucination). Against the implications arise two areas of
objection. One is within the system of
perception though undetected, analogous to the configurational disorder known
(e.g.) by a dyslexic. The other is
outside the system, consisting of perceived accidents not conforming either by
reason of succession (as in the case of “phenomenal star” simultaneous with
“noumenal star-death”) or simultaneously by reason of transcending change in
the nature of the suppositum (as in
the case of transubstantiation, if one indulges the doctrine), to the nature of
the thing as it is. To the first of the
three I would reply that the objection would seem to lose its force of
itself. For if the putative mechanism of
misconfiguration is not in the system, and its product (i.e., the harmony) is
independent of the system, the harmony is still, as independent, of being at
some point and as such the harmony cannot have an origin in disharmony or
nonbeing. The second and third, which
treat more the independent configuration, fail to note the reality of the
accidents (e.g., noumenal star-light; the forms of bread and wine). The noumenal harmony as conveyed is
immediately noted and is valid. The
third, a special case, involves an underlying essential configuration not often
sensuously revealed and is known by a revelation of God to the directees of a
Love that would preserve them from falling into error (so a Catholic should
argue; if certain signs are manifested, given the reality of the sensed, the
argument will carry special force).[1]
0 Comments:
Post a Comment
Subscribe to Post Comments [Atom]
<< Home