Introduction
Prolegomena to Any Future
Noumenology
David C. Braun
© 2006 David C. Braun
Introduction
Carnap[1]
mentions, as if it were worthy of little more than summary treatment, and hardly
a crucial part of his system, the concept of “genidentity,” whereby he means
the continuation of self-identity throughout time, and contrasts it with
identity to state that genidentity is not logically necessary, whereas identity
is. (One surmises that, should he have
admitted the necessary truthfulness of genidentity-statements, Carnap would
have been forced to abandon his denial of Kant’s synthetic a priori
propositions as a genidentity statement necessarily involves more than strict
identity.) But I must first determine
the logical conditions for the possibility of self-identity in one moment in
relation to the environment, which leads me to say that A=A must also mean
A=A+0. Thence I frame the following rules:
(1) As a consequence of A=A, A cannot contradict itself even within
the single moment;
(2) As a consequence of A=A+0, that having the value of 0 is (so to
speak) inert vis-à-vis A (which
cannot contradict itself), a further consequence of which is that ex nihilo nihil fit[2] (I characterize this dual
relationship of A to both itself and its environment as “harmonic”);
(3) As a consequence of all the foregoing, any differing determination
of A that is otherwise A=A and any origination of A in a moment after there is
not A but 0=0 must be by the causal activity of another thing, which produces
change that one comes to know in time;
(4) And, except through causation, A=A must persist throughout time,
thus yielding “genidentity” as the obverse of the law of causation, in conjunction
with the law of noncontradiction. Where
A(Tx) is known
by the law of causation to proceed from A(Tx-i), A(Tx-2), etc., there is a harmony of persistence among them that,
absent interruption according to the manner the constitution of A permits (if
such interruption be possible), A(Tx) will persist as A(Tx+1), A (Tx+2),
etc., as the harmony of persistence is not contradicted from within A. If A is an event constituted so that it may be
discontinued at will (e.g., a thought), there must yet be some antecedent
[thus, e.g., A(Tx-1) would be either the
elements of A(Tx)
as thought aborning or the ground of consciousness of A(Tx), if I may be
permitted that luxury at this point[3]], but I need not seek
a necessary consequent, given my knowledge of the constitution of A, except on
the further showing that the will constituting A is likewise in bondage (as
Luther suggested and Calvin
and classical determinists explicitly held).
These are not the only
dimensions of harmony; the last is one to be introduced through the general
work lying ahead, and will be of crucial importance to the knowledge of the
thing-in-itself, the noumenon beyond possible experience to which Kant referred
in that first Critique. Though much profitable work may be done
by the method of suspending the question of the reality of the perceived to
undertake a phenomenological examination of given experience, I retain my
question of the world even after fruitful description of what is given in
experience and of what is concomitant thereof, as also did not a few who
undertook such descriptions. The work
will show my conviction that the thorny old question can be solved, and some of the
consequences of each possible answer. I
warn that the experience hinted at in the work is paradigmatically (not
necessarily categorically) asserted, and that the reader must devise personal
means of finding (or not finding) a similar experience. My divulging a specific experience to a
reader will create a set of anticipations and render that mode of experience
useless to such in attempting to gain experience of an independent harmony.
That I
persist in using either a singular impersonal pronoun or the first person
singular pronoun wherever possible is a concession to methodological doubt
about the other until I am fully in a position to conclude that another person
is real as given.[4] Counter-skeptics could argue that there is no
point in publishing (as opposed to preparing for personal use) a work that
denies absolutely the other’s reality, except as a colossal exercise in egotism
of the worst sort, an accusation I will not make against the early
Wittgenstein. As a further indulgence of
methodological doubt, I will caution that reference to specific persons named
can be taken as reference to texts appearing in the phenomenal world, and (by
egomorphic analogy) per hypothesin to
their (putative) authors at least until I have reached the point of allowance
of the external world as given. In using
third-person personal pronouns, I try to write gender-neutrally but refuse to
shift from singular to plural (as is customary in these times) for reasons of
grammar as well as of indulgence of methodological doubt up to the previously
mentioned point. (I expect the reader
will take “I” to refer to herself or himself in attempting to follow the
argument.[5])
If the description of the
experienced world without regard to whether it exists is phenomenology, the
knowledge of what is (or is not) beyond experience, including whether the
experienced world is “real,” is noumenology.
Hereto I set my hand, as to the plow.
[1] Der logische Aufbau der Welt, §§128, 159.
[2] See §4, infra. Some hold that one
may not with certainty infer B from A where B is not strictly identical with A
as a consequence of the rule that the only statements certain are those of
personal sense-impressions and analysis.
But A=A+0 allows holding as certain the rule ex nihilo nihil fit.
[3] See §§14, 16, infra.
[4] See §§26, 27, infra; the
point of acceptance of the world will be reached in §27 and 29, infra. To a certain extent, specifically
to avoid the problem of the deceiving spirit. I must rely on the veracity of
God in this also, though I have at this point also a more coherent basis for
allowing at least an organic “other person” by analogy through causation, the
behavior of which likewise suggests an intellectual causal agent as connected
with the body. e.g., through its ability to use intelligent language. As to
that other’s being endowed with freedom and soul, praestet fides supplementum sensuum defectui (to quote a hymn out
of context). See the Appendices.
[5] One last methodological or
logical note is in order. Although “if A, then B, B, thus A” and “if A, then B,
not-A, thus not-B” are rightly characterized as, respectively, the fallacies of
affirming the consequent and denying the antecedent, when “only”
precedes “if” in those statements, they clearly cannot under that circumstance
be fallacious. In the ordinary fallacies, there may be other causes or
conditions for B besides A. The word “only” eliminates those other causes or
conditions.
0 Comments:
Post a Comment
Subscribe to Post Comments [Atom]
<< Home