Preface
David C. Braun,
Prolegomena to Any Future Noumenology
(Copyright
2006 David C. Braun)
Motto:
Gedanken ohne Inhalt sind leer, Anschauungen ohne
Begriffe sind blind.
- I. Kant,
Kritik der reinen Vernunft A51/B75.
[“Thoughts without contents are empty, intuitions
without concepts are blind.”
(tr. of F. Max Müller)]
ta gar aorata autou apo ktisewV
kosmOu toiV poihmasin nooumena
kaqoratai, h te aidioV autou
dunamiV kai qeiothV
[lnvisibilia
enim ipsius a creatura mundi per ea quae facta sunt intel-
lecta
conspiciuntur sempiterna quoque eius et virtus et divinitas.]
- Ad Romanos I. xx.
Preface
I
Any knowledge worthy of the
name is knowledge of the truth. The
convention of the sensible world I know as “Western civilization” assigns the
knowing of truth, at least of the sensible world, to the empirical [or, more
properly, the mathematico-empirical or
logico-empirical] sciences. These sciences treat of the phenomena of the
world, with an eye not merely toward explanation but also toward
prediction. In some enterprises these
sciences are, to some extent at least, so successful that their practitioners
and their supporters come to a confident profession of their exactitude vis-à-vis the truth. The society of this conventional, sensible
world has come to regard these sciences as expositive of the truth; so great is
this regard that, e.g., the law regards scientific facts as facts properly the
subject of judicial notice without further proof (testimonial or otherwise) and
disallows certain types of tests (e.g., polygraphs) for want of scientific
support.[1]
At least one position in the
field of Western thought has appeared that would crystallize the whole of these
sciences into one grand science. [I do
not speak merely of the physicists’ attempt to find a unified-field or
unified-force theory, which some such call a “theory of everything,” though
that name is indicative of the position to which I refer.] This position, that all sciences can be
crystallized into one, translated, means not merely that there is one unified
“science of truth,” but that whatever is not of its component parts is not of knowledge of the truth. Thus, for example, one finds in logical
positivism rejection, not only of metaphysics and systematic ethics, but of all
philosophy as anything other than a mere elucidation
of the meanings of propositions of knowledge [which are neatly divided into
propositions of logic and of facts].
The point of the instant work
is simply to show that any justification of the logico-empirical sciences as exact means to arrive at the truth
must raise questions unanswerable in the framework of such a position and to
answer those “unanswerable” questions which, if unanswered, leave the very
sciences without rigorous justification.
That this bold mission does not merely assume a metaphysical prejudice I
aim to show in the work. Hitherto I have
trusted the validity and end of the logico-empirical
sciences, the object of which is the phenomenal realm. Seeing that an entire field of thought
touches this realm most fundamentally, I might be tempted to elucidate the
foundation of any science of truth on such a phenomenology,[2] though it might be more apt to
consider phenomenology a kind of preface or introductory part of the “science
of truth.” The ground for this
supposition I assign likewise to the main part of this work, although I note
that if phenomenology is a science, it likewise needs justification.
II
Hitherto I have spoken of
philosophy in connection with the branches and indeed the idea of knowledge,
and of the position of logical positivism on philosophy. Philosophy, that “love of wisdom,” is considered
as academic realm and thus divided among different substantive branches
[epistemology, metaphysics, ethics, and — in some schemata — aesthetics]. Logical positivism eschews almost all
philosophy as field of knowledge and substitutes philosophy as activity, as elucidating activity toward
the terms of knowledge in general. This
could in effect be considered an epistemology,
or (more correctly) a doctrine of the possibility and conditions of
knowledge, though cast in terms of “meaning.”
A close reading of the position papers of this now moribund ideology of
science shows that “meaning” refers really to cognitive content. From that is
that position clearly to be seen for what it is, an epistemological doctrine.
The question raised hitherto,
that of the justification of the logico-empirical
sciences, is the question of epistemology vis-à-vis those sciences. As put by another author, philosophy is
thought about thought about a thing.[3] In effect, philosophy is the business of
justifying any means for arriving at any truth. One may find this most apt when
applied to epistemology, though reflection on the sequel may bring to light in
what way metaphysics and ethics fit under this idea of philosophy. [It is to be noted, however, whether for
grounds related hereto or otherwise, that I eject aesthetics as the study of
what is regarded as the beautiful (as
opposed to that of what ought to be so
regarded or not so regarded, and what
ought not to influence my aesthetic sense for what reasons) from
philosophy. I hope it finds its home in the sciences.] As any system of knowledge, even that of
theology [if it be properly a branch of knowledge rather than of mere faith, though
I may come to ask herein to what extent is not science based on mere faith], needs a ground of certitude to be
truly knowledge called, I propose herein to deal with that matter, a matter
fundamental to philosophy as also to science so as to prompt me to call it
fundamental philosophy.
I propose to delve into the
questions of fundamental philosophy, to lay a foundation for the sciences and
for every possible branch of any knowledge.
I do not expect, in so doing, to embrace logical positivism; indeed to
it or its predecessors in interest I may direct comments throughout at variance
with its views or those related views within its tradition. In so saying, I may note with a limited
amount of favor some views, e.g., of Wittgenstein [with whom I am in no wise
completely in agreement, to be sure!]. I
expect to find more fruit for my purposes in the critical endeavors of Kant,
although I take not every view of his as mine.
The careful reader may note my debt to Descartes as well, as also to
others whom I deem it either unnecessary or premature to mention.
III
The most commonplace and basic
statement regarding knowledge relates to its origin, that it originates, in
sense-experience and in intellectual operation.
Doubt arises about the reliability of that knowledge when one considers
the former’s phenomenality, i.e., that
it is what appears, that it appears to be given. For at times the senses are misled, are
visited with dreams or hallucinations, commonly held to exist in and for the
subject alone [even by those who trumpet a facile objectivism]. How, one could ask, might it not be likewise
possible that what one ordinarily would concede to be objectively real might
not be equally tenable as mere dream?
How, for example, would one avoid the question of the Chinese who dreamed
he was a butterfly and arose to ask whether he were not in truth a butterfly
that dreamed it was a man?[4]
The first answer one might be
tempted to offer, almost certainly in good faith (but without great reflection,
immediately), is that such a notion as that of Zhuang Zhou made no sense, was irrational. For,
one could argue, by noncontradiction, the true identity would remain
constant. I might dream I was a
butterfly, a cat, a stone; I would arise to be what I continuously regard
myself to be in waking. Thus any
constant self I ought to credit as actual.
One notes from the above, on
careful examination, an argument proceeding from a dearth of empirically
gathered material, by ratiocination,[5]
the latter part of the source
of knowledge set forth at the beginning hereof.
Moreover, this operation is closely allied to certain fundamental laws,
usually elucidated in logic as laws of
thought, especially the principle of noncontradiction (i.e., it is false
that A is not-A). But many have
complained that (1) reason is a prostitute; (2) syllogism begs the question;
(3) reasoning might in some case mislead and is thus uncertain. The initial response is that, as long as the
thinker avoids fallacies and adheres strictly to the definitions pertaining to
the harmonic, the result will be as certain as the law of noncontradiction,
which pertains to the harmonic. [Of
syllogisms proceeding from universals to particulars, for example (the case
citable as circular or question-begging), the result is not fallacious to the
extent of the harmony of definitions of the universal in question and other
particulars thereof. So if, e.g.,
Socrates died, Plato died, Aristotle died, etc., and I am of their form also, ceteris paribus I should likewise die,
although some would point with glee to my downfall regarding Enoch or Elijah
(if they are believers) only if they ignore my caveat.] One should recall,
moreover, that “definition” should be taken in the sense of that set forth,
whether by experience or by voluntary act, which is incorrigible; as a good
example I cite direct experience of, e.g., the whiteness before me in
sight. Whether that page is “real” or
“dreamed,” it nevertheless is experienced as white. From this should it be clear that logic based
on the laws of thought [of identity, noncontradiction, and the excluded middle,
to be specific] can operate validly with respect to that which is harmonically
defined, or given as A=A in its moment at least. [This is not to say that we have no
definition without a sensory experience’s given, though we clearly begin with
the field of definitions.]
But again we return to the
question of Zhuang Zhou’s dream: Is not
self-experience itself, that incorrigibility of definition which, together with
the general proposition of causation [ex
nihilo nihil fit], to be discussed below, assures the validity of an
existent Cartesian ego, beset at
times with the problem of harmonicity vel
non of its object? To what
experiences should I give priority; to what experiences should I give no value
in any task? If I suppose that the ego [or its ground] is harmonic, thus
admitting those experiences to have value which are not of contradiction, do I
not appeal to a matter not within my sensation, i.e., a subsisting ground, thus
setting as answer what cannot be achieved by my equipment for knowing? Is it not possible that, outside my
experience, there is nothing harmonic, nothing consistent, perhaps even
nothing?
The problem, succinctly put, is
this: Is the sensory, harmonic world in
and for the subject alone? Aside from
the perceiving subject, are that world and the ego [as] nothing at all? Can we legitimately, without confusion,
without violating rules of the faculties of knowledge, speak of truth? Of “knowledge” itself? I expect to set forth, in showing in what way
these terms are legitimate, a showing
that my questions are legitimate and meaningful in a cognitive sense. To the phenomenalists and others whose
objections I noted above, I say that any giving priority to the harmonic
experiences of the self, without accepting the nonharmonic ones except as
topics for discussion in terms of a causal deep structure and a theory of
independent objects, must lack any justification in their thought’s
undergirding. This bankruptcy of
phenomenalism is manifest in its [confessed?] inability in the aforementioned
area of critical importance, not only to the possibility of self-knowledge but
also to that of any predictive, descriptive science. Part hereof has yet to be elucidated; the
matter set forth below will shed light thereon and develop its implications
more fully. I confess, however, that
phenomenalism places a difficulty in the way which, if insurmountable, will
render “knowledge” and “truth” impossible, except in the most trivial sense.
IV
Ere I leave these introductory
remarks to pass to the meeting of the challenge, I must recommend a study
preliminary to the instant inquiry. As I
assume that the reader is familiar with these writers, I can save much space
and avoid needless duplication by pointing in the directions hereinafter set
out. The familiar may nod in
recognition; the unfamiliar do well to pass thereto. I did not choose the first
motto of this work vainly; it is an important sentence of Kant’s justly famous
first Kritik. This is in no wise to say that I agree
with Kant’s entire system, as the work will abundantly show. That work assumes familiarity with much of
the prior thought of Europe, but I think it sufficient for the reader to know at
least the Discours de la méthode of
Descartes. Although herein are echoes of
themes found elsewhere, the foregoing named books will suffice as background
herefor.
The structure of the remaining
work, in the most general terms, I expect to fall into the following
scheme: First, I will set forth the
above problem in full context of the possibility and modi of cognition. Thence I
will essay to answer the question.
Lastly, I will develop the implications to be derived from that which,
in answering the questions, I have set forth.
No less than this do I wish to have as my goal, although I confess at
this point that I may well leave certain implications thereof undeveloped, nay,
untouched.
[1] E.g., Fed.
Rule Ev. 201(b)(2); Calif. Ev. Code §452(b);
§90.202(12), Fla. Stat., for former; Frye
v. U.S., 54 App.D.C. 46, 293 F. 1013, 34 A.L.R. 145 (1923); Kaminsky v. State, 63 So.2d 339 (Fla.
1952), as to the latter.
[2] In
Appendix III of this work I discuss difficulties involved in actual positions
taken by individual historical phenomenologists, even positions taken by
phenomenology’s founding father. Those difficulties make it impossible for me
to give unqualified endorsement to those positions, even though I can well
appreciate the value of phenomenological contributions to the development of
philosophical knowledge.
[3] R. G.
Collingwood, The Idea of History, p.
1 (London 1975).
[4] I quote, e.g., Tchouang-tseu, oeuvre complète, ch. 2,
at p. 45 (Paris 1986): Jadis Zhuang Zhou rêva qu’il était un papillon voltigéant et satisfait de son
sort et ignorant qu’il était Zhou
lui-même. Brusquement il s’évoilla et s’aperçut avec étonéent qu’il était Zhou.
Il ne sait pas si c’était Zhou rêvant qu’il était un papillon, ou un papillon
rêvant qu’il était Zhou. [In English: “Once Zhuang Zhou dreamed that he was
a butterfly flitting about contented with his condition and incognizant that he
was actually Zhou himself. Suddenly he
awoke and discovered to his astonishment that he was Zhou. He did not know if he were Zhou dreaming that
he was a butterfly or a butterfly dreaming that he was Zhou.”]
[5] For now I will neglect the
distinction between Verstand and Vernunft, one not a few may regard as
overemphasized or illegitimate at present, though this is not necessarily my
view.
0 Comments:
Post a Comment
Subscribe to Post Comments [Atom]
<< Home